Teacher's Guide - Class Planning Guide
Guide Homepage
| Planning your Course
| The Absolute Basics
| Class Planning Guide
| Essays | Against
Lectures | Reading
List I Adam Morton's Sample Course
The
Contract
Part 1
- [1] [2]
[3] [4]
[5] [6]
| Part 2
- [7] [8]
[9] [10]
[11] |
Part 3 -
[12[13]
[14] [15]
Planning Information
| Comments on Sections | Test
Chapter 8
Planning
information:
8.1 essential - read for class
8.2 essential - work through - rehearses 8.1
8.3 essential - read for class
Box 16 optional - email
8.4 essential - read for class - work through - rehearses 8.3
8.5 essential - read for class
8.6 essential - work through - rehearses 8.5
8.7 less essential - work through - rehearses 8.5 - email
8.8 less essential - harder
8.9 less essential - work through - rehearses 8.8 - email
8.10 essential but needn't be covered in class - read
The absolute core of this chapter is 8.1, 8.2, 8.3, 8.4, 8.5,
8.6
Chapter
8 - Comments on Sections
8.2 It is not important to get an explicit list of the (a),
(b), (c) factors for each case, though if you have a large
class divided into smaller groups this will define the task
for them. But you should nudge the discussion so that in each
case the non-utilitarian moral concern emerges. In (1) honesty,
principle, in (2) responsibility for particular people, respect
for life, in (3) responsibility, respect, implicit promises.
(And so on; there are different ways of expressing the concerns.)
8.3 This will not be easy reading for many students. (But
it's as simple as I can make it and still state Kant's views.)
So you must make sure it has been digested.
8.4 (i) objects to (1); (ii) objects to (3); (iii) objects
to the inference from (3) and (2) to (4); (iv) objects to
the inference from (1) to (2). The objections to the inferences
will be harder to spot than the objections to the premises.
If students note that, e.g. (iii) is targeted at (4) then
you can push a little bit harder and ask what it shows is
wrong with the argument, since after all it may at first seem
just to be dogmatically denying the conclusion. Of course
the objections may not be fatal, and you should ask both whether
the points made in (i) to (iv) are right and whether they
would scupper the argument even if they were.
The relationship between (iv) and the inference from (1) to
(2) may be hard to see. (iv) could be taken as an objection
to (1). But even if we grant (1), that motive is all that
matters when we judge actions, the question remains whether
it is all that a moral agent should aim at. (iv) suggests
that it is not, and that a moral person should try to be competent
as well as well-intentioned. So that is something, besides
acting morally, that they should aim for.
I have marked this "read for class" as I would want
students to have time to think about the relationship between
the points and the structure of the argument.
8.6 In (a) the consequentialist is Norbert and the deontologist
is Martha. In (b) the consequentialist is Paolo and the deontologist
is Ottavia. In (c) the consequentialist is Quinn, the deontologist
is Sandra, and Roberta is a rule-utilitarian. (Rule-utilitarianism
is defined in 8.8, but you don't need even to mention it.
The point is that Roberta's line seems to have elements of
both deontology and consequentialism.) The students may find
(b) the hardest to diagnose; the point is that Paolo is focused
on the grandchildren getting what they want - his consequentialism
maximizes want-satisfaction rather than happiness - while
Ottavia thinks that there is a fixed way that children in
her family should behave. It would be good if the discussion
brought out that there is a variety of things that different
consequentialists can maximize and a variety of principles
that deontologists can hold sacred. (a) should provoke a general
discussion of ends justifying means. You may have to interject
to point out that consequentialism doesn't give a completely
free hand to adopt means to desirable ends: the overall balance
of good over bad results has to be positive. The class may
well think that shooting the drunk was wrong but shooting
the would-be atomic bomber would not be wrong. Ask them what
would be allowed to prevent the bomber. Torturing innocent
people, shooting down airliners, pre-emptive bombing of a
neighborhood? (It is not obvious that the resolute consequentialist
position that says Yes to these is indefensible. But it does
need defending.)
8.7 This also rehearses 8.5, and should lead
to the interesting questions: does a deontologist (from the
students' point of view: an anti-consequentialist, who believes
that there are things you mustn't do ever) have to say that
you must always tell the truth, and never break promises?
Is this just a sort of a trap that the consequentialist is
trying to lure him into? The heading "Taking your mother's
advice" alludes to an incident in Ann Fine's Taking the
Devil'sAadvice - which could be called "never marry a
philosopher" - which links with the theme here.
8.9 This section picks up on ideas from the
end of 8.8, but it can be worked through without first reading
8.8. It might be a good to ask the class first, after they
have read all four arguments, which are the more powerful
and challenging ones. Then classify them as consequentialist
or deontological. There may be an interesting clash then between
students' apparent loyalties and the arguments they find persuasive.
(1) and (4) are consequentialist in spirit, and (2) and (3)
deontological.
8.10 This chapter ends not with a perspective-giving
section by me but with an activity that asks the student to
put the strands of the chapter together herself. It is not
essential to do this. But it could be fun. It would be best
to divide the students into small groups of two to four -
even a class that is not normally subdivided would be split
up for this one - and provide each group with a photocopy
of the Jerry/Manuella contributions, cut into strips for them
to put into order. The intended result is M2, J2, M1, J3,
M3, J5, M5, J4, M4, J1. It would be interesting to know if
there are other orders that make both logical and conversational
sense. This activity could also be used as a test for the
chapter.
Chapter 8 - Tests
First test - the activity of 8.10
Second test
For each of the questions below circle the two
wrong answers to it:
(1) How does a morality that centers on motives
differ from a morality that centers
on consequences?
(a) Thinking about consequences will commit you to lying.
(b) Sometimes the motives of an action are unacceptable even
though the
consequences are desirable.
(c) People can do moral acts from bad motives.
(2) What does Kant's categorical imperative
say?
(a) You should act on principles that you could want everyone
to follow always.
(b) You should act on principles that would have good consequences
if everyone
followed them.
(c) Treating people as ends in themselves is the same as acting
out of a desire to
be moral.
(3) How can the idea that there are things no
one should ever do be defended?
(a) By giving examples in which acts that no decent person
could perform have
good consequences.
(b) By giving examples in which acting from moral principle
results in disaster.
(c) By arguing that if some acts are not forbidden then horrendous
results will
follow.
(d) By arguing that to act morally is to accept rules restricting
your behavior.
(4) How can consequentialism require more of
us than conventional morality does?
(a) By forbidding us to tell lies, even to avoid disaster.
(b) By requiring us to consider the consequences of our actions
for all people
equally.
(c) By allowing us to perform intuitively immoral actions
if they have good
consequences.
(5) How can deontological ethics require
more of us that conventional morality does?
(a) By forbidding some actions, whatever the consequences.
(b) By requiring us to contribute to famine relief.
(c) By requiring us to think of others as ends in themselves.
|