Teacher's Guide - Class Planning Guide
Guide Homepage
| Planning your Course
| The Absolute Basics
| Class Planning Guide
| Essays | Against
Lectures | Reading
List I Adam Morton's Sample Course
The
Contract
Part 1
- [1] [2]
[3] [4]
[5] [6]
| Part 2
- [7] [8]
[9] [10]
[11] |
Part 3 -
[12[13]
[14] [15]
Planning Information
| Comments on Sections | Test
Chapter 4
Planning information:
4.1 essential - read
4.2 less essential - suitable to work through in class - rehearses
4.1
4.3 essential - suitable to work through in class - rehearses
4.1
4.4 not essential but desirable - read for class
4.5 work through - rehearses 4.4
4.6 essential - read for class
4.7 essential - work through
4.8 not essential but desirable - read for class - work through
- email
4.9 optional topic - email
4.10 optional topic - read - email
4.11 essential - read for class.
The absolute core of this chapter is 4.1, 4.3, 4.6, 4.7, 4.11.
The chapter is a lot richer if 4.4 and 4.5 are included though.
The pedagogical aim of this chapter is to make
the students consider seriously the idea that you can get
clearer about moral issues by thinking and arguing. Positions
much weaker than a full moral rationalism will allow thought
to grip morality, of course. But moral rationalism is easily
understood and relates clearly to the rationalistic epistemology
of the previous chapter. An obstacle here is a use of a naïve
moral relativism that students will use more as a protection
against disturbing thoughts than out of real conviction. I
think the best attitude to it is gentle ironical subversion
- you don't really think that, do you? - rather than frontal
assault. Plato is valuable here because his ideas are challengingly
alien while every now and then hitting a note that seems just
intuitively right.
Chapter
4 - Comments on Sections
4.1 This should be a quick and not very challenging read that
students can easily get through before class. It is followed
up by two actitivity-based sections, 4.2. and 4.3. Either
would be adequate, though I have listed the longer 4.3 as
essential because it touches more central questions. (But
if you are doing only one, it makes a big difference which
one you find more interesting.)
4.2 The crucial point in doing this activity is to make sure
that the differences between the claims (1) to (4) are vivid.
The Rama and Sitta questions are meant to do this, but you
may need to dwell on the issue, and you may prefer other ways
of doing it. There are two main connections with moral rationalism.
First, that the most natural candidate for an a priori moral
principle needs to be carefully formulated: there are lots
of choices. (The same would happen with arithmetic or geometry
or set theory.) Second, that when you think about even the
simplest moral principle in an abstract way you move into
confusion, from which you can emerge in a very different place.
There is also a point about philosophical method here. If
you don't focus hard on what an assertion literally says,
you run it together with similar claims which can have quite
different consequences. A "Chinese whispers" activity
can bring this out: one person whispers a simple but syntactically
indirect sentence into the ear of another - "the only
necessary people are good people," for example - who
whispers it into the ear of another, and so on for four or
five more. Then each says what she heard: they tend to be
logical as well as phonetic variants of the original.
4.3 This is a big activity and will take a whole class session.
It would be best if the students had read it in advance to
make the material somewhat familiar. Working through the activity
is straightforward though. You shouldn't hurry; everything
that needs to be explained or discussed along the way should
be, and it is better to take two classes to get through it
than to force it. The important moment comes at "Political
Arithmetic" when the justice-inducing force of the various
factors is assessed. I expect that imbalance of power and
proportion in the bottom group will come out as decreasing
justice and voluntariness and social mobility will come out
as increasing justice. Resentment of inequality is a less
predictable factor. I would guess that reactions to it are
very sensitive to the background of the students. In any case,
students are less likely to agree about it than the others.
Consensuses and disagreements should be noted, and the possibilities
for thinking out moral/political issues noted.
Disagreements are likely about the relevance of resentment
and of social mobility. Does it make a society less unjust
if few notice or mind (consider the position of women in a
traditional patriarchy)? Does it make a society less unjust
if by hard work and a bit of luck more able people can get
status and goods that their initial positions denied them
(but what about the less energetic or less talented)? Discuss
these for their own sake, only making the methodological point
about moral rationalism as a kind of a footnote.
Sophisticated students will want to distinguish between injustice
and other ways a society can be flawed. Keep this distinction
in mind as a possible diagnosis for disagreements that are
not being clearly articulated.
The directions in the text presuppose that you have a large
class which is divided into smaller groups. It is clear what
to do and what to omit if the class is functioning as one
group.
4.4 This section and the next are about Plato's Republic,
a topic that you could skip. But I would advise doing them,
in order to show how one famous philosopher did hope to do
ethics by pure reason. They thus link closely to 4.3, on the
topic of justice. The design of institutions is an obvious
entry point for ideas about reason in ethics. 4.4 is a purely
textual section; it is meant to be read for a class in which
4.5 is worked through.
4.5 This will take a whole class period. (Or more. Again,
let it take what it needs.) The students will have to read
through the passages from Plato in class, even if they have
looked through them in advance. The activity directed at claims
(1) to (6) is one that you can approach very directly with
any group. It might be best to begin with eliminating the
claims classified as C: not conclusions of the passage. (4)
and (6) should appear as non-conclusions: (4) because Glaucon's
argument, that in his thought experiment the just person would
behave unjustly, presupposes that there is a difference between
just and unjust, and (6) because Glaucon thinks that in normal
conditions there is a motive for acting justly (but it is
a self-interested motive). Sorting out the remaining four
claims into (A) and (B) is harder. As I read the passage,
the A-claims, the main conclusions, are (2) and (5), and the
B-claims, the more incidental ones, are (1) and (3). For (1)
and (3) appear as conclusions of subarguments leading to (2)
and (5). Some students may read the passage differently, and
you should ask them what structure they think the argument
as a whole has. (The question should make sense to them from
chapter 2.)
The suggestion in the text of putting the classification in
a table and comparing results is best done very quickly, just
to see if there is a lot of disagreement between individuals.
If there is, you will have to go carefully through the points
made just now.
If the class is going to take two sessions to work through
this section, a natural place to break is between this activity
and the following one, based on a different passage.
The second activity of this section also centers on a passage
from the Republic. This one argues for a much less intuitively
natural conclusion, though one that Plato himself is suggesting
rather than rejecting. The activity does not involve structuring
the argument in the passage, but rather considering three
arguments that roughly fit it, and comparing them. You will
need enough time for the class to read and digest all three
(or you could do just the first two). Of the objections (a)
to (e), I would say that (b) and (d) are relevant to (ii),
(c) is relevant to (i), and (e) is relevant to (iii). (a)
is a dummy, relevant to none of them, stuck in to make sure
everyone is awake.
The fact that, though the arguments have the same conclusion,
they are vulnerable to different objections should be pointed
out as generally important. (There can be crappy arguments
for true conclusions.)
To my mind the third argument, the most elaborate, is the
nearest to being convincing. But you should be able to get
some respect for all of them, and for Plato's general line
here, by presenting them as ways of developing the thought
that you can't have a good society unless the people in it
are good.
4.6 This description of the pros and cons of moral relativism
is deliberately neutral. In fact it tries to elicit some sympathy
for the view, to help the students articulate their own sympathies.
Some of the issues then raised, explicitly and in the back
of the students' minds, are then worked through in 4.7
4.7 It should not be difficult to make this activity work.
It would help to have a straw poll in advance, in which students
identify themselves as being generally for or generally against
moral relativism. (No fence-sitting allowed.) Then work through
the arguments one by one, making sure they are understood,
and recording how convincing students find them. (There is
no right and wrong about this.) Then force the pro-relativism
students to identify the anti-relativism arguments they find
most challenging, and vice versa. If, as is most likely, they
hold on to their positions in spite of admitting the force
of contrary arguments, they will be searching for holes in
the arguments. Then you're away.
4.8 Another activity on moral relativism, this one designed
to elicit intuitions against it. Turnbull's actual position
is quite subtle. While his description of the Ik is often
used to make the point that one can describe a culture objectively
and also say that it is morally awful, he explores the possibility
that these judgments are superficial: they are the kinds of
things that people can say when they are not starving. The
activity I describe could be a way of getting a structured
discussion of these issues going, but you might also have
the students read all eight passages from Turnbull and then
just let them take the discussion where they want to.
4.9 The relation between law and morality is not essential
here. But it does give a good lever on issues about moral
relativism since to a large extent what is legal clearly is
relative to time and place. So if relativism is not true we
should expect some things to be legal but wrong, and the questions
about the moral force of different laws are meant to bring
this out. I would suggest going quite quickly through the
reactions to the For and Against arguments and then focusing
on the possible laws 1 to 6. It is quite likely that when
you have stated the questions about them the discussion will
take on a life of its own. That's fine, of course.
4.10 A nonessential topic that will interest many students.
The quotation is from The Second Sex. Notice how although
existentialism seems at an opposite extreme from moral rationalism,
the de Beauvoir quote seems to express a very definite moral
attitude. Is this an inconsistency?
4.11 The debates in and provoked by this chapter are likely
to be inconclusive. This final section offers a diagnosis
of what lies behind the disagreements, and some suggestions
about how a position might combine the insights of both rationalism
and relativism. Students could read this section on their
own, with no classroom rehearsal. But if you want to discuss
it in class and want a structured activity, then 4.8, if not
already done, would serve. The connection to make is that
4.11 suggests that we should reject both extremes, and that
the descriptions in 4.8 invite us to reject relativism while
Turnbull's reflections invite us to reject rationalism.
Chapter
4 - Test
(This test is based on the objectives stated at the beginning
of the chapter.)
For each question circle the best answer
(1) Why is moral rationalism often based
on a principle of impartiality? (a) because it is fair (b)
because it looks like a true principle that we can know by
use of reason (c) because Jesus, Confucius, and several modern
philosophers have all defended the principle.
(2) What factors can increase the justice of a society? (a)
equality of opportunity; (b) equality of happiness; (c) equality
of unhappiness.
(3) How does Plato think that he can prove what an ideal society
would be like? (a) by making mathematical calculations; (b)
by describing an ideal person; (c) by imagining societies
and then thinking hard about their good and bad qualities.
(4) Which of these are (beginnings of) arguments against moral
relativism? (a) what is legal in one country is illegal in
another; (b) we can judge whether the principles people in
a culture live by are fair or unfair; (c) we should tolerate
other cultures.
5) How is existentialism different from moral relativism?
(a) existentialism is concerned with values individuals adopt
while moral relativism is concerned with values cultures adopt;
(b) existentialism says that life is meaningless while moral
relativism says that life has the meaning your culture gives
it; (c) existentialism says that people make their own values
and moral relativism says that there are only values relative
to a culture.
6) Which of the following should we expect of a moral philosophy?
(a) a list of right and wrong actions; (b) a way of understanding
the values of all people; (c) a description of what disagreements
over right and wrong are disagreements about.
|