Teacher's Guide - Class Planning Guide
Guide Homepage
| Planning your Course
| The Absolute Basics
| Class Planning Guide
| Essays | Against
Lectures | Reading
List I Adam Morton's Sample Course
The
Contract
Part 1
- [1] [2]
[3] [4]
[5] [6]
| Part 2
- [7] [8]
[9] [10]
[11] |
Part 3 -
[12[13]
[14] [15]
Planning Information
| Comments on Sections | Test
Chapter 1
Planning
information: [see below for explanations
of the labels]
1.1 essential - read for class
Boxes 1 and 2: optional reading - email
1.2 essential - work through - rehearses 1.1
1.3 less essential - work through
1.4 work through - email
1.5 essential - read for class
1.6 optional reading: not to be worked through in class
Box 3: optional reading: not to be worked through in class
1.7 less essential - work through - email - rehearses 1.5
1.8 less essential - work through - email - rehearses 1.5
1.9 essential: read for class - should be discussed in class
1.10 less essential - work through - rehearses 1.9
1.11 less essential - work through
1.12 essential - read for class - should be discussed in class.
1.13 essential - work through - rehearses 1.12
1.14 less essential - work through
The absolute core of the chapter is sections 1.1, 1.2, 1.5,
1.12, 1.13.
Here and in other "planning information"
sections, "read" means the class should be asked
to read the section, whether or not it is discussed in class.
"Read for class" means that the class should read
the section before a class meeting, if the topic is being
covered. Usually that meeting will then work through a section
that rehearses, follows up, the material in the section they
have read. "Work through" means that the section
has material for a group activity clarifying the material
in it or another section. "Email" means that the
section provides material that could feed an email discussion
between students or between students and teacher. Some sections
are classified as "essential," others as "less
essential," which generally give different ways of covering
the same or closely related ground as the essential topics,
and "optional," which are stimulating topics that
are related to the theme of the chapter.
There are four sections that it is essential
for the students to read in advance of class meetings (1.1,
1.5, 1.9, 1.12). For each of these sections there is at least
one follow-up section that elicits discussion of it. For 1.1
there is 1.2, for 1.5 there are 1.7 and 1.8, for 1.9 there
is 1.10, and for 1.12 there is 1.13. So if you plan to get
through this chapter in a week you should schedule the required
reading so that all three essential sections are read in advance,
and in the class after they have read one of them a follow-up
section is worked through. If you think your class is intellectually
quite sophisticated and you would like to get through the
preliminaries fast, you could cover the absolute core in two
classes.
The pedagogical aim of this chapter is to establish
the idea of questioning beliefs, even firmly held and apparently
obvious ones. The student should leave the chapter understanding
that it is not obvious what is obvious, and that the activity
of looking for reasons for beliefs can have interesting and
unexpected results.
Chapter
1 - Comments on Sections
1.1 This section should be read by students
as a background to the rest of the chapter. It doesn't need
class discussion, though students may want to raise questions
about it.
1.2 You should get the students to write down their scores
on the questionnaire before you get to the crude classification
of intellectual personality or the more subtle diagnosis.
The discussion of the differences between students' answers
should tend toward comparisons of the advantages and disadvantages
of having the various personalities. What true and false beliefs
are different personalities more or less prone to acquire?
What practical activities are helped or hindered by having
one or another intellectual personality? That is not to say
that you should squelch a lively discussion if it is not going
in this direction. But you should try gently nudging it toward
some evaluative questions.
Students may protest against the labels that the diagnoses
force on them. Ask them to say why the labels don't apply.
Is it that the definitions used in the text are misleading?
Is it an accident of the examples that were used? Why is the
label unwelcome: what's wrong with being a dogmatist or having
unconventional beliefs?
1.3 Note that at least four of the claims have a religious
aspect. It is thus likely that differences between students
about their plausibility will be related to different attitudes
to religion. The section should encourage a discussion on
how such disagreements are resolved. So you might choose two
people whose views are very different on one claim, for example
(5) or (9), and ask each of them what discovery might make
them agree with the other. Then, once this had established
the idea that one can imagine evidence which one doesn't expect
to find, you might ask the class what evidence might make
them less sure of (1), (6), or (11). Another purpose of this
section is to undermine the idea that one either believes
something or disbelieves it. Often one has no opinion, or
has a slight tendency to believe which falls short of belief.
So you might take (1), (6), (11) and ask which of them is
more certain and which has the greatest chance of turning
out to be false. Then move on to (4), (10), or (5), (7) -
depending somewhat on which ones the class classifies as convictions
- and ask the same questions. Is it equally hard to imagine
evidence against (3) and (4)?
1.4 This section is meant to bring out the fact that no authority
is self-interpreting: one always needs to make decisions about
what words mean and whether a principle applies to a particular
case. You might discuss the problems of taking the Ten Commandments
as a mechanical guide to morality. What does "thou shalt
not kill" really mean (does it forbid killing in self-defense
- does it permit capital punishment)? What counts as adultery?
On the physics and chemistry textbooks example, you will probably
find that the students easily see that problem (a) arises
with (2), (b) with (3), and (e) with (1) and (4). They may
need more prompting to see that (f) arises with (5) - does
the law of the conservation of energy apply to human "energy"?
- and that (c) arises with (6) - if the book mentions chemical
or physical topics but contradicts other textbooks are we
to count it as a textbook or as an imposter? Problem (d) is
an all-purpose worry about any supposedly self-sufficient
source of information, especially when combined with (e),
but it doesn't particularly apply to any of (1)-(6).
The class will not need convincing that chemistry and physics
textbooks could not be an all-purpose guide to belief. Ask
them which of the problems that arose with the textbooks would
also apply to other sources of belief: sacred books such as
the Bible, perception, the things your parents taught you.
1.5 This section has the heaviest prose so far, so you should
check that the students found it readable. If they did not,
each time they have read a section in preparation for a class
you will have to spend time making sure that they were not
baffled by it. The point of the section is to explain the
appeal of trying to deal with the fear that we might be caught
in a closed-belief trap by trying to show that many of our
beliefs are certain, that there is no way that they could
be false. You will probably find that the students do not
find it plausible that most of our beliefs are certain, especially
after working through the previous sections. But most of them
will think that some of our beliefs are completely certain,
and some of them will think that it is these beliefs that
give us the only assurance we can have that everything we
believe is not one systematic delusion. With luck, you will
find that some students agree with this idea and others do
not, so that it is clear that this is both an appealing and
a controversial strategy.
You might find it useful to read section 2.1 before leading
a discussion of this section, especially the discussion of
how the authority of traditional belief might constitute a
closed system of beliefs.
1.6 This is included just for stimulation and amusement. The
philosophical points are (a) how hard it is to know the truth
even in simple situations and (b) the intuitive links between
skepticism and paranoia.
Box 3 This is also not intended for classroom discussion.
The main point is the idea - associated with Quine and Duhem
- that any belief can with enough ingenuity be reconciled
with any evidence. Material such as this, and other boxes
and sections such as 1.6 that are not meant for classroom
discussion, may still provide a source of allusions and examples
for discussions prompted by other sections. And reading them
can help students get in the right frame of mind to have reactions
to other sections.
1.7 I think it would help to say explicitly to the class before
working through this section: your inclination is probably
not to take the tree-worshipers seriously, but working through
the section might convince you that there could be a whole
way of looking at the world which makes much more sense than
at first seems possible, and from that point of view your
beliefs seem absurd. (This is a way aliens might think, and
they might be right.) So you will have to make the students
write down serious objections to the tree-worshipers' view
of the world, and then do some quick thinking eliciting responses
to the objections. It would be best to have the class pool
their objections, and then work together to think of the tree-worshipers'
replies. The example of the flat-earthers is similar. If you
work through this part of the section yourself in advance
you may be able to run the discussion in a less regimented
way in which you simply ask the class for evidence that the
earth is not flat, and for each piece of evidence show what
standard belief a flat-earther might challenge in replying
to it. One hard abstract question you might slowly find your
way toward is: given that a clever enough flat-earther is
unlikely to be caught in outright contradiction, is there
something lacking in their whole system of beliefs, after
they have made the changes necessary to preserve their position,
which gives it the overall characteristics of a delusion?
1.8 This section is nonessential but raises two potentially
very useful issues. First, how social pressure works to make
one believe things and sometimes disbelieve what one's own
senses and intuitions tell one. The workings of the party
on Winston can be taken as an exaggeration of the ways the
desire to conform and the threat of being different work on
each of us. Second, more subtly, how when we lose our grasp
of how to tell what is true we begin to lose our grasp of
what the difference between truth and falsity is. Winston
begins to think that perhaps the party can change the past
by declaring that things have happened.
1.9 The aim of this section is to separate different things
that "doubt" can mean, in order to focus on the
philosophically most important sense, in which doubt does
not aim at showing that a belief is false but that we do not
have good grounds for holding it. (Or, yet more sophisticated,
that we do not know whether we have good grounds.) To a philosophically
trained person this distinction is as simple as the difference
between rejecting a conclusion and rejection as a conclusion.
But if you put the point this way to most beginning students
a few eyes will light up while most of them will remain completely
blank.
One point to making these distinctions is to show that you
can be a philosophical skeptic without being insane. And you
can be a philosophical skeptic about religion or morality
- ask what our reasons are for believing in God or thinking
that rape is evil - while being a Christian or a moral person.
1.10 This section rehearses the distinctions between kinds
of doubt. You will find that different students classify the
doubts differently in part because of different interpretations
of the motives and meanings of the speakers. For example,
in (7) some students will take Belinda to be defending the
possibility that murder is justifiable, and others will take
her to be ironically challenging our confidence that our values
are always correct. So the real work is likely to be done
in teasing out the reasons why students' answers deviate from
the "obvious" responses, which are: (1) [(5)] vulgar
doubt; (2) [(5)] (6) [(7)] (8) careful doubt; (3) (4) [(7)]
philosophical doubt. (I have put in [square brackets] cases
that could be classified in two ways equally naturally.)
1.11 Make sure the students understand the "strongly
agree or disagree," so that a firm atheist should put
4 by (a). As with 1.2, some students may challenge the labeling
that the questionnaire applies to them, and this fact is to
be exploited rather than glossed over. The most promising
route to a philosophical discussion starts with the fact that
some - perhaps most - of the students will come out as more
skeptical about some kinds of beliefs than others. Why is
this? Why might someone be dogmatic about science but not
about religion? Why is someone who is dogmatic about religion
likely not to be skeptical about moral matters? (The answer
to this last is not nearly as obvious as it may at first seem.)
1.12 This section introduces an important dimension to philosophical
doubt and skepticism, to test and elicit reasons for our moral
principles. The second half of the section brings out the
tension between moral seriousness - thinking that some things
are really wrong, and not just a convention we all agree to
go along with - and skepticism. The resolution is philosophical
doubt: one can take the wrongness of, say, murder with full
seriousness and still ask where the wrongness comes from.
1.13 The obvious answers are that Carina is cynical, [Arthur]
and [Eduardo] are questioning, Betty and [Eduardo] are pathological,
and [Arthur], Daniel, and Felicia are philosophical. (Again
[square brackets] indicate cases that could be taken two ways.)
Some may not think that Eduardo is pathological, and indeed
he is a normal child, but I defined the term in a specific
way to include everyone who does not understand the words
adults use to express moral beliefs. One promising route to
a discussion here is to ask whether the philosophical doubters
can be sincere in their moral beliefs while still asking for
reasons for them. A particular doubt may arise about Felicia,
who seems to lack some features of a good person. Let that
discussion go where it may, as long as it remains clear that
the point is that a moral skeptic does not have to be a cynic,
not that no moral skeptics are cynics.
The questions about which ones to associate with and which
ones to permit to act on their convictions are there to elicit
opinions about the value of moral skepticism. With luck, some
people will say that they would rather not associate with
Felicia, but that she should be allowed to go around undermining
others. Probing why they say this will bring up some interesting
issues.
1.14 This section covers a historical topic that fits well
with the themes of this chapter, but is not essential to it.
Some students will be relieved to see famous philosophers
like Socrates and Plato appearing, to reassure them that they
really are studying philosophy. There's no point in doing
this section unless it takes a whole class session, at least,
and the students have read it in advance. (Of course, one
option is to take two weeks and read the whole Meno, using
this section as a guide.)
Of the four possible conclusions for the selection from the
Meno all can be found in the passage. So none are really wrong.
But the main conclusion, the one the others are meant to support,
is that the definition of virtue as power is wrong. It is
only by understanding the dialogue this way that we make it
an instance of Socratic skepticism, in which people are shown
not to understand basic issues as well as they think they
do.
At the very end of the section the question is raised of whether
you have to be able to define a word in order to understand
it. The "Juliet" example is there to suggest that
perhaps sometimes people do use a word without knowing much
about what it denotes. (Love-struck teenagers may not know
much about what love is, and to that extent have a weak grasp
of the meaning of "love.") You might also allude
to the test for legal responsibility sometimes invoked, that
one can be held responsible for crimes if one understands
the difference between right and wrong. If Socrates was right,
would any of us pass this test?
Chapter
1 - Test
Most students will find most of these questions easy. Some
may provoke a useful moment of reflection. And some may be
worth discussing afterwards, especially if most members of
the class get some questions wrong.
Mark each of the following assertions as True
or False:
All beliefs are equally true.
Whenever someone believes something false there is evidence
against it.
False beliefs can usually be defended against true evidence.
A moral skeptic is always cynical about moral matters.
A philosophical skeptic thinks that other people have false
beliefs.
Religious dogmatism means believing in God.
If you know something you don't believe it.
If a belief is certain then there is no evidence against it.
If there is no evidence against a belief then it is certain.
In a false belief trap someone has so many false beliefs that
they cannot understand the reasons why their beliefs are false.
The certainty assumption gives the only way out of the false
belief trap.
Religious dogmatism is the only way of avoiding moral skepticism.
Note 1: Sometimes in response to a true/false question students
may find that they know that one answer is the one that the
course has been prompting, but in fact they believe the opposite.
You could consider using a variant answering system in which
students can write, for example, "F" rather than
F, or the like, and then write a couple of sentences of explanation
at the bottom or on the back of the test. Marks would be awarded
for knowing what answers the course is prompting, but intellectual
honesty would be its own reward.
Note 2: Students have access to this website
too. You may worry that they will have seen the test in advance.
I don't see this as a big worry, as if they have learned the
right answers from seeing it in advance they will have reflected
on the material. You may worry about students passing the
answers on to one another. In that case put the questions
in a different order, rephrase some of them, and add a few
more of your own. You needn't say in advance what day you
are giving the test.
|