Teacher's Guide - Class Planning Guide
Guide Homepage
| Planning your Course
| The Absolute Basics
| Class Planning Guide
| Essays | Against
Lectures | Reading
List I Adam Morton's Sample Course
The
Contract
Part 1
- [1] [2]
[3] [4]
[5] [6]
| Part 2
- [7] [8]
[9] [10]
[11] |
Part 3 -
[12[13]
[14] [15]
Planning Information
| Comments on Sections | Test
Chapter 6
Planning information:
6.1 essential - read
6.2 essential - read for class
6.3 essential - work through - rehearses 6.2
6.4 essential - read for class - work through
Box 12 not essential - email
6.5 essential - read
6.6 essential - read for class
6.7 essential - read for class
6.8 less essential - work through
6.9 less essential - work through - rehearses 6.10 - email
6.10 essential - read
The absolute core of this chapter is 6.2, 6.3, 6.4, 6.5, 6.6,
6.7
The pedagogical strategy of this chapter is to show that we
do not have to equate reasonableness with certainty. We can
distinguish the more and less reasonable among things that are
doubtful. A critical discussion of Hume is the main device for
doing this. The point about reason is linked to ideas about
toleration, as explained in 6.5 and 6.6, and these links are
explored in the rest of the chapter. It is essential to the
strategy to cover either 6.6 and 6.7 or 6.8; if time is short
you could skip one of them.
Chapter
6 - Comments on Sections
6.1 This section just puts the chapter into perspective. It
should be clear without classroom explanation, but students
should read it.
6.2 This is an exposition of Hume, trying to elicit sympathy
for his position. It goes with 6.3, which works through actual
short passages of Hume.
6.3 Hume's English is old enough for students to have to read
it slowly. When working through this section in class have
the students go directly to the modernized paraphrases in
[square brackets]. (My scholarly colleagues would not have
forgiven me for leaving out Hume's actual words, though I
can choose translations of Plato or Descartes into clear modern
English.) The correlations between (a) to (d) and the passages
should be no problem. The very abstract arguments (2) and
(4) seem to me to have force against the general line in A,
though they don't connect with it very specifically; (3) is
a line that could be taken, but Hume has an obvious reply
to it ("some people want pain; what's so unreasonable
about that?" (1) is a quibble that could be avoided by
rephrasing the example. (5) is to my mind the most forceful:
is Hume saying you can rationally want just anything, including,
for example, wanting A or B but wanting neither A nor B, or
wanting A more than B and B more than C and B more than A?
(6.4 develops this point.)
Of (i) to (iv), (iii) seems to me the only defensible choice.
In using this section to prompt a discussion I would first
have the class read the passages and then very quickly check
comprehension with (a)-(d) , explicitly or informally, before
focusing on (A). I'd pose the question "Is A right?"
and hope that things developed from there. (1) to (5) would
be brought in only if the discussion needed some shaping.
(It would be best to have asked the class to read the section
in advance, thinking about the (1) to (5) activity in particular.)
This could then lead on to a discussion of how (A) relates
to the other passages. What is the attitude to thought and
reasoning that it expresses? And after that had got going
you could ask if any of (i) to (iv) are good expressions of
the possibilities raised.
6.4 This section makes an important subtle point, that the
fact that reasoning rarely gives certain conclusions doesn't
prevent us from distinguishing good from bad reasoning. It
makes this point under the cover of making a cruder point,
that there is good and bad reasoning, but the examples it
uses are ones where certainty doesn't apply.
It is a mixed exposition and activity section. The examples
at the beginning of the section are not linked to any formal
activity, though you could easily focus on one or another
example and ask for their reactions to it and what they think
it illustrates. The activity with (A) to (H) is much more
structured. I think the way to make it work is to raise the
examples one by one and ask what is wrong with the thinking
of the person in question, eliciting informal descriptions,
which you then link to (1) to (6). The intended links are
(A)-(1), (B)-(5) or (6), (C)-(4), (D)-(2) or (5), (E)-(1)
or (2), (F)-(3), (5), or (6), (G)-(5), (H)-(1). As the alternatives
suggest, I don't think it's obvious what labels to apply.
Perhaps the students can come up with some better ones. I
expect it to be uncontroversial that the people in (A), (C),
(D), (E) are exhibiting some kind of irrationality - and that
is enough to make the main point. Other cases are going to
be controversial. (H) is interesting in showing that a belief
can be logically flawed but the person holding it might be
described as just making a mistake rather than being irrational.
What would we have to add to the description to make Henrik
irrational?
6.5 Although this is a short exposition which students should
be able to take in without classroom explanation, this section
is important to the overall argument of the chapter. It makes
the connection between reason's surviving the loss of certainty
about facts and its surviving the loss of certainty about
values. It is definitely not obvious that this symmetry holds.
All the chapter argues is that some naïve reasons for
thinking that when certainty goes reason is powerless are
not convincing in either case. Some students may want to argue
that although we have good inductive and other methods for
getting conclusions about the world which we can reasonably
believe, though they will sometimes have to be revised, we
do not have anything analogous for values. Encourage these
students. Ask them to find out exactly how much of this chapter,
and of chapter 11, they have to disagree with.
6.6 This is to be read in advance of a classroom session in
which 6.7 is worked through.
6.7 Although this section is on the surface a test of tolerance
(and most students will think that toleration is a virtue,
and its opposite is bigotry) a less apparent purpose is to
distinguish kinds and reasons for giving and withholding tolerance,
so that it is no longer so obvious that it is a virtue to
tolerate all alien values, however deeply held.
The important thing in this activity is to react to the examples,
so you should allow time for the point of each one to emerge,
rather than rushing to the point-scoring. In (6) the class
may not find good examples of acts that are (arguably) harmless
to others which someone might consider immoral. Suicide by
terminally ill people is one example; consenting homosexual
activity is another. Examples (6) and (7) link with issues
arising in 6.8, so you can curtail the discussion of them
if it is taking too much time and you will later be getting
to 6.8. Example (5) links to issues in 6.9, so the same applies.
The examples do not contain descriptions of really repulsive
values: no religions based on child abuse, no brainwashed
subservient women, no public burning of widows, no racist
theology. The discussion should be lively without these, if
the pulls in different directions implicit in the examples
are exploited. But if things seem too bland and disagreements
are not emerging, you could always spice things up by asking
if the reactions to (3) or (6) are unchanged if a suitably
higher-charged example is used instead.
If the discussion has gone well, there is no need to linger
over the scoring. You should have students score themselves
quickly, and soon after rate themselves as type 1 or type
2 tolerant or intolerant. If the discussion has dragged, you
may linger on whether the labelings produced by the scoring
are fair or accurate, what "tolerant" and "intolerant"
mean, and whether the type 1/2 tolerant/intolerant diagnoses
do catch the reasons behind individuals' patterns of response.
(See the note above for section 1.2.)
The activity at the end of the section is directed at a large
class that can be broken down into smaller groups. It won't
work if examples (6) and (7) have already been talked out,
so you have to anticipate doing it, or keep it in your mind
to do if you have time.
6.8 There is no preceding expositional section for this largely
activity-based section, because the quote from Mill with which
it begins is clear enough on its own. So if you are working
through this section in class you should first make sure that
the quote has been read and digested. In a small group you
could then go first to (i)-(vi) and ask each of them what
problems it makes for the harm principle, after a short discussion
of each, fitting (A) or (B) to it (or deciding that neither
fits.) My answers would be that (A) fits (ii), (iv), (v),
(B) fits (i), (iii), (vi). That is not to say that they are
all equally powerful objections to the principle. To my mind
(v) has no force: some may disagree. (vi) may seem cryptic
It could be filled out with an example of someone spying on
his neighbors' love-making: he could be argued to be doing
them no harm, except inasmuch as they object. One thing to
be careful of is the direction in which (B) objects to the
principle. The problem is not that the principle ignores the
harm done, e.g. to atheists at the thought that others worship
gods, but rather that it includes this distress as harm, thus
giving a ground for interfering with religious (or irreligious)
activity.
In a larger group you must either explicitly ask for each
of (i) to (vi) which of (A), (B) it fits best, or divide the
group into subgroups with instructions to discuss each of
(i) to (vi) and then fit it to (A) or (B).
The first thing to do in discussing the revisions (1) to (3)
is to be clear about how they differ from the original. It
shouldn't be hard to elicit from the class that (1) adds a
rationality requirement, (2) specifies kinds of damage, excluding
those that arise just because of people's attitudes, and (3)
combines the amendments of (1) and (3). After quickly discussing
the content of (1) to (3) you could ask which of the four
possibilities - Mill's original principle and the three modifications
- is too strong - allows too much to be forbidden too much
- and which is too weak - doesn't permit us to forbid things
we might have good reason to.
The second half of the section discusses Mill's attempt to
give motivation for toleration. Again the quote is clear on
its own, and you need only briefly make sure it has been understood,
in which case you should include the clarifying paragraph
I have added, leading down to (I) and (II). Your aim then
is to get a discussion going on whether in fact it is in the
public interest to have free discussions. Consider each of
(a) to (d) and whether there should be unrestrained discussion
on such topics. Then ask whether the reasons for unrestrained
discussion look like (I) or (II). It might help to cite the
example of societies such as China, where the government has
the aim of producing a sophisticated, technologically advanced
society but without allowing open discussion of political
or religious matters. Is it obvious that this cannot succeed?
If not, does this suggest that free discussion is pointless,
or that it is justified on some other grounds than general
benefits to society? It might also help to pose explicitly
the question of whether open discussion of religious questions
will lead to agreement on true religious beliefs. It is easy
to doubt this, but also easy to think that freedom of expression
on religious matters is still a good thing. This suggests
that its justification is something other than (II) (and something
other than (I) in that monolithic religious societies are
often harmonious and efficient).
The last part of the section is subtle, but important in that
it makes the link with certainty. The Mill quote here is not
as clear as the previous two, and needs the gloss I provide.
If there is time, an open discussion of the issues raised
in the final paragraph of the section could make many things
fall into place. If there is no time for this, it is a good
idea to ask the class to read through the last part of the
section on their own.
6.9 The aim of this section is to suggest that when we have
strong scientific reasons for believing something this does
limit the resources we are willing to commit to investigating
alternatives, and this can be a kind of intolerance of them.
So when discussion or investigation has a cost we use our
best estimates of probability to help decide whether the cost
is worth incurring. I would work through this section simply
by taking each example in turn and discussing it, in the class
as a whole or divided into smaller groups, guided by the questions
I pose. Then ask the whole class whether their (individual
or group) reactions to (C) are different from their reactions
to (A) and (B). The difference could take many forms besides
the degree of disagreement mentioned in the text. It could
be that different reasons for action are relevant in the different
cases. For example, the desire to have a society in which
different cultures and beliefs flourish may be relevant to
(C) but not to (A) and (B). Or there may be variations on
(C) which contrast more sharply with (B). For example, suppose
that what the newcomers in (C) need to stay in business is
use of a resource such as the park, and you are chair of the
committee that decides access to it. Variations on (B) are
also possible: suppose that the request is not from some religious
group but from supporters of some scientific theory which
is not completely impossible but which the majority of scientists
think is wrong.
6.10 This section rounds off the chapter. It is not necessary
to discuss it in class, but it would be desirable for the
class to read it.
Chapter 6 - Test
(This test is based on the objectives stated at the beginning
of the chapter.)
For each of the questions below circle two acceptable
answers:
(1) The reason that Hume thought that many beliefs
are not based on reasoning is that he
thought that :
(a) most people are irrational; (b) induction is not an operation
of reason but of
habit; (c) many beliefs are not based on anything that makes
them certain; (d) anyone
can reasonably believe anything.
(2) Hume thought that any desire is as reasonable
as any other because:
(a) reasoning tells you how to satisfy your desires, not which
desires to have; (b) no
one satisfies very many of their desires, whatever they are;
(c) any desire can be
based on any true assessment of the facts; (d) evil people
are more rational than
virtuous ones.
(3) Hume's understanding of reason leaves out
the following factors:
(a) reason is an emotion; (b) beliefs can be inconsistent;
(d) desires can be incoherent
(d) there are better and worse ways of handling data that
is not certain.
(4) It can be objected to Mill's harm principle
that:
(a) it allows my actions to be restricted by your reactions
to them; (b) it allows
people to do themselves harm as long as no one else is affected;
(c) it encourages
libel; (d) it permits people to hold views which are offensive.
(5) Reasons for tolerating views which
you think are wrong are:
(a) in the end no belief is right or wrong; (b) the open discussion
of these views
may harm no one but those who choose to discuss them; (c)
discussion of them may
show that they are true after all; (d) the people holding
these views are not evil but
just mistaken.
|